Assess the proposition that the majority judgments in Liversidge v Anderson were wholly subversive of the principles both of the rule of law and the sovereignty of Parliament as Dicey would have understood them
The ‘orthodox’ conception of Parliamentary sovereignty, as set out by AV
Dicey, consisted of two propositions: that Parliament has the right to
make or unmake any law, and that no other individual or body has the
power to overrule any law made by Parliament. He likewise conceived of
the rule of law as composed of several propositions: that punishment be
only due for breaches of law established by the courts, and that
everybody (including the government) is subject to the same
laws.AV
Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution
(1885).
The case Liversidge v
Anderson[1942]
AC 206, [1941] 3 All ER
338.
concerned a plaintiff, using the alias of Liversidge, who accused the
Home Secretary, a Mr Anderson, of wrongful imprisonment. The plaintiff
had been detained under Defence Regulation 18, which stated that “If the
Secretary of State has reasonable cause to believe any person to be of
hostile origin or associations … and that by reason thereof it is
necessary to exercise control over him, he may make an order against
that person directing that he be detained”; no reason was specified in
the order made for Mr Liversidge’s arrest, and as such one was applied
for to the High Court. None was provided, and on appeal the House of
Lords held that, although the regulation referred to ‘reasonable cause
to believe’, it was not to be interpreted objectively, but rather that
the Home Secretary had absolute discretion in deciding whether there was
reasonable cause.
The conflicts with the Diceyan conception can be summarized briefly. Firstly, in terms of Parliamentary sovereignty, it would appear that the courts are being granted the power to redefine statute; where Parliament required the Home Secretary to have ‘reasonable cause to believe’, the courts in effect refused to enforce this requirement. In fact, this phrase had been absent from the initial draft of the regulation, and then explicitly introduced (although Parliamentary privilege would have prevented the drafting history of the regulation from being introduced as evidence).
Secondly, and relatedly, this appears to undermine the rule of law by failing to apply the same laws to Government ministers as to everyone else; this is particularly evident in the majority judgments in the House of Lords, where the decision was justified by reference to wartime necessity. There is also a broader concern regarding the predictability of the legal system: that an individual should be able to know the law, to have a reasonable understanding of how it might be interpreted, and to know the nature of the charges against himself or herself; all of these could be said to have been absent in Liversidge, and more generally in any situation where the courts interpret a statute so broadly.
This is the position taken by Allen in the Law Quarterly
Review;Carlton
Kemp Allen, ‘Regulation 18B and Reasonable Cause’ [1942] LQR
232.
in a highly critical article, he expands upon
Lord Atkin’s minority opinion, arguing that the term ‘reasonable cause’
had an established meaning (i.e., that it implied an objective test).
For Allen, the decision in Liversidge not only departs from
established principles of statutory interpretation, but reflects a novel
(and unjustified, to judge from his use of sarcasm) deference to the
authority of the Secretary of State.
The majority judgments were based on a principle of purposive
interpretation: according to Viscount Maugham, ‘we should prefer a
construction which will carry into effect the plain intention of those
responsible … rather than one which will defeat that intention’. This
principle was echoed by Denning LJ some years later, in Magor and St
Mellons RDC v Newport
Corporation,[1952]
AC 189, [1951] 2 All ER
839.
when he argued ‘We do not sit here to pull the language of Parliament
and of Ministers to pieces and make nonsense of it [but] to find out
the intention of Parliament and of Ministers and carry it out …’.
(Ironically, the House of Lords now called this line of reasoning ‘a
naked usurpation of the legislative function’.)
However, questions of ‘the intent of Parliament’ are inherently fraught: while it may have been clear in Liversidge that Parliament intended to permit the Home Secretary to issue orders for detention on certain grounds relating to security, was it also clear that Parliament intended that such an order required only subjective justification, rather than objective? Lord Atkin thought not; in his opinion, the decision of the majority amounted to a granting of complete discretion to the Home Secretary, requiring nothing more than good faith which, he thought, could not be disproved. Moreover, he provided extensive examples of the usage of the term ‘reasonable cause’, arguing that it was settled law that this referred to an objective test, and described the idea of a subjective test as ‘fantastic’.
Indeed, it can well be argued that the intent of Parliament, as a body of individuals with many varying opinions on any given matter, can only be determined by reference to what they have agreed to in the text of a statute; this is an argument in favour of progressively stricter forms of statutory interpretation. While it may not be necessary to restrict interpretation to a literal one, since interpreting the statement entirely absent of any context may be impossible if not nonsensical, it does require strict reference only to documented sources of Parliamentary intent: other parts of the statute, similar statutes, and Hansard, for example. The House of Lords’ criticism of Denning’s judgment in Magor included the implication that his attempt to ‘fill the gaps’ had been based in guesswork, rather than any principled determination of what Parliament really had intended. Indeed, arguments have been made for the inclusion of a ‘statement of purpose’ in the preface to an Act of Parliament, in order to provide a guideline for interpretation.
Conversely, Goodhart, writing in support of the majority
judgment,AL
Goodhart, ‘Liversidge v Anderson’ [1942] LQR
3.
suggests that in reality every decision can
only be subjective, being based on fallible individual judgment; Allen
is disparaging of this line of reasoning, pointing out that ‘he would
not find it easy to persuade any Court that there is no difference
between having a broken ankle and thinking that one has a broken ankle’.
Indeed, a significant part of Goodhart’s article seems more political
than jurisprudential; he expresses concern that Atkin’s dissent ‘seems
to assume that executive officers have little respect for the law unless
there is an appeal to the Courts against their acts’. He, like Denning
some years later, places faith in the Secretary of State to do only what
is permitted by law. Like the majority of the House of Lords, Goodhart
departs from Dicey in his willingness to permit punishment without
establishing a breach of law before a court, on the apparent grounds
that the Secretary of State can be trusted not to depart from the
regulation.
However, the Diceyan perspective does not tell the whole story, and it is important to note the limits to this interpretation. In particular, Dicey’s conception of Parliamentary sovereignty is descriptive, not normative: it is an explanation of how Parliament had appeared to work up until that time, rather than defining how Parliament would continue to work. This has been shown most clearly by developments over the past several decades relating to the interaction between domestic and European law, especially following Factortame. Furthermore, Dicey’s theory of the rule of law was influenced by the dominant ideologies of his time, an individualist liberalism that would not admit of the possibility of a system of public law distinct from the ordinary private law. This too has been departed from over the course of the 20th century, with the development of a more robust system of judicial review.
Nor was Liversidge unique in its deference to executive authority;
numerous instances can be found both since that time. While, of course,
the Government has never been entirely unconstrained by judicial
oversight (the Pergau Dam
caseR
v Secretary of State for Foreign and Commonwealth Affairs, ex parte
World Development Movement Ltd [1994] EWHC 1 (Admin), [1995] WLR
386.
being a noteworthy example), there have been others where the courts
have been unwilling to restrict ministerial discretion, especially when
the question of national security is raised. For example, in ex parte
Adams,R
v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex parte Adams [1995]
All ER (EC)
177.
the court found that, while the Home Secretary’s decision under the
Prevention of Terrorism (Temporary Provisions) Act 1989 was in principle
judicially reviewable, he was not under any duty to reveal the reasons
for the decision, since to do so might require the disclosure of
sensitive information; thus, the court could not determine whether the
decision was illegal or unreasonable. Suggestions that the decision was
in fact politically motivated (the plaintiff was a Northern Irish
politician and former MP, invited to Parliament by an Opposition MP
against the wishes of the Government and its allies) were therefore to
no
avail.JAG
Griffith, The Politics of the Judiciary (5th edition, Fontana Press,
1997) 198.
A similar situation had arisen earlier
in ex parte
Hosenball,R
v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex parte Hosenball
[1977] 3 All ER 452, [1977] 1 WLR
766.
in which an American journalist was deported for national security
reasons, which the Home Secretary refused (on request) to explain
further; the Court of Appeal upheld the decision, with Denning MR
asserting that rules of natural justice did not apply in cases involving
national security, but that in England, anyway, “[ministers] have
never interfered with the liberty or the freedom of movement of any
individual except where it is absolutely necessary for the safety of the
state.”
In summary, the decision in Liversidge is difficult to reconcile with a Diceyan understanding both of the rule of law and of Parliamentary sovereignty; but it is not so unique or divergent that we can safely assume that the decision itself is wrong; instead, we must also consider the possibility that Dicey was, at least in part, wrong, and that if the judgment is to be criticized it may need to be on other grounds than a strict adherence to 19th century jurisprudence.
List of Cases
- Liversidge v Anderson [1942] AC 206, [1941] 3 All ER 338
- Magor and St Mellons RDC v Newport Corporation [1952] AC 189, [1951] 2 All ER 839
- R v Secretary of State for Foreign and Commonwealth Affairs, ex parte World Development Movement Ltd [1994] EWHC 1 (Admin), [1995] WLR 386
- R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex parte Adams [1995] All ER (EC) 177
- R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex parte Hosenball [1977] 3 All ER 452, [1977] 1 WLR 766
Bibliography
- Allen CK, ‘Regulation 18B and Reasonable Cause’ [1942] LQR 232
- Dicey AV, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (1885)
- Goodhart AL, ‘Liversidge v Anderson’ [1942] LQR 3
- Griffith JAG, The Politics of the Judiciary (5th edition, Fontana Press, 1997) 198